Wednesday, February 11, 2015

Against Avakianism - Part 4

Excerpt from "against avakianism" by Ajith, Secretary of the former Communist Party of India (Marxist-Leninist) NAXALBARI, today merged in the CPI 


TRUTH, CLASS INTERESTS AND THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD

The tendency to envision or explain reality in a fashion suited to one’s views or immediate political, organisational needs has been present in the ICM for long.[1] It became particularly pronounced during the Comintern period and was compounded by Stalin’s metaphysical errors. Mao broke away from this. He insisted on ‘Seeking truth from facts’ and declared ‘No investigation, no right to speak’. Through his philosophical works and practice, he reiterated the Marxist position on the independent existence of objective reality. All ideas are ultimately derived from it. And that is where they must be tested for their veracity.
In the course of critiquing Avakianism we have repeatedly seen how its adherents ‘bend’ words so that opposing views become amenable to their polemics. This is an acute manifestation of the tendency to explain reality in a fashion suited to one’s views. However, without the slightest of scruples, Avakian asserts that he is digging out instrumentalism and that this is his unique contribution. Moreover, Mao too is accused of the sin of sanctifying instrumentalism. The proof is supposed to be seen in the May 16 circular issued during the Cultural Revolution. According to Avakian it asserted that “…there is such a thing as proletarian truth and bourgeois truth…”[2] Let’s take a look at that circular.

This is what it said, “Just when we began the counter-offensive against the wild attacks of the bourgeoisie, the authors of the outline raised the slogan: 'everyone is equal before the truth'. This is a bourgeois slogan. Completely negating the class nature of truth, they use this slogan to protect the bourgeoisie and oppose the proletariat, oppose Marxism-Leninism, and oppose Mao Tse-tung's thought. In the struggle between the proletariat and the bourgeoisie, between the truth of Marxism and the fallacies of the bourgeoisie and all other exploiting classes, either the East wind prevails over the West wind or the West wind prevails over the East wind, and there is absolutely no such thing as equality.”[3]
The accusation of the Avakianists is centred on the words “class nature of truth”. Objective reality is equally the same for the proletariat and the bourgeoisie. Therefore, attributing a class nature to it opens the path to instrumentalism. That is his argument. But is that all there is to it? The May 16 circular was opposing the capitalist roaders’ argument that ‘everyone is equal before the truth’. What exactly was being indicated by ‘truth’ in that context? Reading down, one sees that this was not about objective reality. It was about ideologies, thinking. When the bourgeoisie in the party said that ‘everyone is equal before the truth’ they were not debating the existence of objective reality irrespective of class. They were demanding that the proletarian state must allow equal space to bourgeois views. This is why the circular insisted that there cannot be equality in the struggle between ‘the truth of Marxism and the fallacies of the bourgeoisie’.[4]
This is plain enough. So why did Avakian resort to misinterpretation in order to charge Mao of instrumentalism? There is of course the Avakianist urge to pull words out of context. But that is not all. Avakian’s belaboured criticism of ‘class truth’ reflects a deep flaw in his conception of material reality and the process of comprehending it. Earlier we saw how he reduced material necessity faced by revolution solely to the economy. Even that was grasped in a partial manner. What we will now see is how Avakianism labours to eliminate class from the process of understanding social reality and conflates the natural and social realms.
 Not just the ‘fallacies of the bourgeoisie’, the ‘truth of Marxism’ too is not objective reality as such. Through an ongoing process of ‘seeking truth from facts’ Marxism can grasp this reality in a qualitatively deeper and more  comprehensive manner as compared to the bourgeoisie and other classes. The ‘truth of Marxism’ can stand the closest to objective reality because of its class partisanship. Its quality of being thoroughly scientific, of starting from objective reality and making that reality the test of its understanding, is indissolubly bound up with its partisanship.  This is so because the class it represents, the proletariat, is the only one that has a basic interest in comprehending reality to the fullest extent possible. That derives from its being the only class that must take the revolution all the way to the emancipation of all humanity to achieve its own liberation.
Mao explained, “The Marxist philosophy of dialectical materialism has two outstanding characteristics. One is its class nature: it openly avows that dialectical materialism is in the service of the proletariat. The other is its practicality: it emphasises the dependence of theory on practice, emphasises that theory is based on practice and in turn serves practice. The truth of any knowledge or theory is determined not by subjective feelings, but by objective results in social practice.”[5] Note how Mao insists that dialectical materialism has a class nature. As we know, Marxism’s scientific approach and method flows from this philosophy. But the Avakianists do not accept this intrinsic relation between the class partisanship of Marxism and its scientific approach. In their view, “Marxism is a scientific understanding of nature and society that reflects reality as best and as thoroughly as mankind can do at this stage of history. And Marxism reveals the possibility and the necessity of proletarian revolution – it is partisan.”[6]
According to this argument, mankind has a science known as Marxism. It’s a science that, among other things, reveals the need for the revolution of a specific class. And that is why it becomes partisan. In other words, the class basis of the scientific approach of Marxism is denied. Its scientific approach is separated from its class character.[7] This is clarified in their statement, “Marxism is partisan and it is true; but one cannot say Marxism is true because it is partisan.”[8] As we noted earlier, the ‘truth of Marxism’ is not objective reality as such. It isn’t endowed with knowledge of this reality just by being partisan to the proletariat. But the capacity of Marxism to grasp truth, and to do that far deeper than any other, is inseparable from its partisan character. In that sense, it is true because it is partisan. [9]
Further down in the same piece of writing the RCP accepts that “Marx and Engels wanted to change the world; without that orientation they would never have discovered the truths that they did discover.”[10] Here, the vague term ‘orientation’ replaces the proletarian class interest with which Marx and Engels had identified. Without in the least diminishing the astounding intellectual labour of Marx and Engels, it must be emphasised that they were prompted by this partisanship and not some super heroic propensity for being scientific. They arrived at this through a process of realising the inability of existing theories to correctly grasp reality and learning from the class struggles going on.[11]  If not for that partisanship there would be nothing propelling them to the discovery of the scientific principles and method of Marxism. Conversely, if not for the development of this scientific grasp, their partisanship would have remained utopian.
The Avakianists highlight Marx and Engels’s application of scientific principles and the scientific method in separation from the class partisanship that guided them. They then confuse the issue by dragging in the matter of ‘constructing truth’ as opposed to ‘discovering’ it.[12] We must certainly discover truth, not construct it. However, the point of debate here is the role of class interests, partisanship, in enabling one in this task. Marxism emphatically declares and upholds this relation. The Avakianists deny it. Where does this lead them to?
 This can be understood by examining some of their arguments: “Comrade Ajith argues one of the cornerstones of the CRC’s deviation was its departure from proletarian class stand. The philosophy and method it applied for analysing categories such as individual or democracy, its idealism, metaphysics and ahistorical treatment of the issue, was a consequence.” (emphasis added) Here Ajith is clearly separating “class stand” from philosophy and method. However, for Marxists “philosophy and method” are central to the proletarian ideology, not something that merely “results” from class stand. What does “proletarian class stand” mean separated from the philosophy and method that together with class stand make up proletarian ideology? Really it can only mean simple class feelings – for example, identification with the masses, hatred of the exploiting classes, and so forth.”[13]
Class stand, viewpoint and method no doubt make up the proletarian world outlook. But that does not mean that they don’t have their own specificities. Nor does it negate each one of them impacting in its own way upon the others. In the history of the CRC’s deviation this was quite evident. A document written by those who had ruptured from the CRC noted, “Though the CRC, CPI(ML) played an important role in defending Marxism-Leninism-Mao Tsetung Thought, the tendency of the leadership to deny the universality of this ideology was present from the very beginning.”[14] But the way it got manifested was not directly centred on philosophy or method. It emerged as a tendency that argued for seeking answers to new questions in views advanced from non-proletarian stands on the plea that they have not been dealt with by the leaders of the proletariat. The document criticised this and said, “New things and knowledge are constantly emerging in this world. The proletariat must grapple with them and continuously develop its ideology and practice. But it cannot ignore the fact that all of these new things have a class character. So the vanguard party should analyse them from its own class stand point and outlook. It should carry out synthesis on the basis of the fundamentals of its ideology. Otherwise it will become eclectic and liberal in its ideological approach, opening the door to revisionism.”[15]
It could be argued that ignoring the class character of new phenomena is already a deviation in philosophy and method. Yes, it certainly is. But that does not mean that the particular features seen in the emergence and subsequent course of development of a deviation cannot be separately identified. In the specific instance of the CRC, the weakening of class stand soon led to weakening and overturning the mainly correct views it had on philosophy and method during its initial period. This was the experience being cited in the writing criticised by the RCP. It does not in the least bit suggest that primacy must be given to “proletarian class stand” as opposed to “proletarian philosophy and method”. It was drawing lessons from a specific example of deviation from proletarian ideology to stress the importance of class stand. There was a reason for doing that. The arguments on developing ideology being raised by the RCP were already pointing to the disastrous direction it was taking. Having experienced the deviation of the CRC, indications of their attempt to separate the scientific outlook and method of Marxism from its class nature were all too apparent to us. Their response confirmed this. They accuse us of separating class stand from philosophy and method precisely in order to counterpose them and side-line the former.
More deeply, by minimising the role of “simple class feelings” the RCP displays a dismissive attitude towards the foundational significance of class position, the material position of the class. All the three components of the proletarian world outlook - stand, viewpoint and method - flow from this material reality; they are ultimately determined by it. While class hatred or feelings cannot substitute for class stand, there cannot be a class stand that excludes them. All the members of a Maoist party, regardless of their class origins, have to struggle to acquire a proletarian world outlook. But there is a qualitative difference in this matter between those who come from the working class and others. In the case of the latter, particularly those coming from the ruling classes or middle classes, declassification is decisive. The lessons of the erstwhile socialist countries amply prove that this is not just a matter of learning Marxist theory. The class line of a Maoist party, building it primarily among the basic classes, consciously tries to draw on the strengths given by the class position. That is correct and necessary. It plays an important role in retaining the proletarian character of the vanguard. The RCP’s approach of one-sidedly highlighting the decisive role of theory in ideology downplays this.
Chang Chun-chiao’s correct identification of theory being the most dynamic factor in ideology is driven by the RCP’s logic to a one-sided position that makes it the sole dynamic factor.[16] It observed, “… a theory which departs from MLM will inevitably corrupt any genuine proletarian feelings.”[17] The converse, a weakening of class stand leading to theoretical deviations and corruption of ideology, is practically denied. This is then taken to the next level. The danger I had drawn attention to, “… reducing Marxism to a methodology cut off from its proletarian stand and partisanship.” is attacked as an example of insisting on the “… opposition between “stand and partisanship” and methodology.”[18] Thus they deny even the possibility of such an approach despite its being widely seen among intellectuals.[19] No, there is no opposition between Marxist methodology, its viewpoint and stand. But there is a powerful tendency which portrays and tries to use the philosophy of dialectical materialism and its methodology as tools that can be employed by anyone, regardless of their class stand. This was seen in the CRC’s positions.[20] We see its repetition in a new form in Avakianism’s views on the scientific nature of Marxism. It is further exposed in its positions on the ‘fundamentals of Marxism.’
The RCP argued, “… Ajith is raising the questions of “fundamentals of Marxism” as a special category that somehow can escape from the realm of critical examination. In so doing, Ajith presents Marxism, its “fundamental principles,” not as a scientific method and approach, not as both a product as well as a tool of social investigation, but essentially outside this process.”[21] Notice how the ‘fundamental principles’ of Marxism are reduced to ‘method and approach’.
What was the context in which this issue was raised? I wrote, “Leaps in the history of the development of proletarian ideology are marked both by rupture and continuity. One sees a dialectical interaction between the two. Continuity through rupture, and rupture made possible by continuity. In terms of what was discussed above, this can be described as standing firm on the basic principles (or fundamentals) of Marxism by developing them through creative application to correspond to contemporary social reality and tasks. Both revisionism and dogmatism deny the dialectics of rupture and continuity. But what is it that enables one to grasp this dialectics? The universal truth of Marxism, its class stand, method and, above all, its revolutionary mission. If this is called into question, then we lose our mooring.”[22] Evidently, the fundamentals of Marxism are not being posed as something above critical examination. The necessity to develop them by rupturing from views that do not correspond to contemporary social reality is acknowledged. But if this is not done by standing firm on the universal truth of Marxism it will deviate. Therefore, the development of Marxism is not simply a matter of putting up its fundamental principles for re-examination in a general sense. It demands the application of the universal truth of Marxism in concrete situations which include the realm of theoretical practice also. Mao wrote, “Marxism must necessarily advance; it must develop along with practice and cannot stand still … However, the basic principles of Marxism must never be violated, otherwise mistakes will be made.” “It is revisionism to negate the basic principles of Marxism and to negate its universal truth.”[23] This is indeed an exacting task. How do we decide what constitutes the ‘basic principles’, the ‘universal truth’ of Marxism? How do we differentiate them from others that are not so essential?
I attempted a definition by suggesting that such principles should be distinguished from the models thrown up by their application. This approach is of use in some contexts. Let’s take an important issue currently under debate, the dictatorship of the proletariat. Its vital necessity during the period of transition from capitalism to communism is an inviolable basic principle of Marxism. Now, the specific way this was implemented in the Soviet Union was at one point considered as THE application and sanctified as a fundamental. Yet, its errors were later criticised and Mao developed a qualitatively different application. The ‘fundamentals/models’ distinction can be of assistance to understand this. But, even then, it is of limited value. The examples listed out by the RCP of principles that were considered fundamental at one point and later abandoned as mistaken or outmoded certainly shows this.[24] Yet, it remains a fact that a satisfactory resolution of what constitutes the essential fundamental principles of Marxism still remains unfulfilled. Its stand, viewpoint and method no doubt lie at the core. But that is not all. Ideological positions too are part of it.
Ideology, MLM, is understood as the body of work and method of the great leaders of the international proletariat. Over the course of its development through advances and setbacks in application, as well as due to basic changes in the world, the ICM has deepened its grasp and raised the level of its understanding. Some parts of what were considered as essential parts of its ideology have been discarded or transformed. The Maoist grasp is not the same as a Leninist or Marxist one. But its advanced grasp is not merely a matter of rupture. The insights and foundations of Marxism-Leninism are essential to it. Thus, the question of the basic principles of Marxism directly relate to the universality, the universal truth, of ideology. The RCP view of treating the fundamentals as ‘method and approach’ in the name of being scientific tends to deny this.
Hence they take offence for saying that, “Though new advances in Marxism arise from concrete application and verification through practice in a particular country they contain universality precisely because they are guided by the fundamentals.”[25] The accusation is that “He does not argue they are universal because they are universally true, but rather because they correspond to, or were based upon, the “fundamentals” of Marxism. Gone is the objective criteria of truth, that it corresponds to material reality, and in flies another opposite criteria where the truth of some idea or theory (its “universality”) is determined by its consistency with the premises on which it was based.”[26]
When ‘concrete application and verification through practice’ is specifically mentioned, it should be obvious that the objective criterion of truth is not in any way denied. So then what was be argued for?  The line of a Maoist party in a country is developed by creatively applying the universality of MLM in the concrete conditions obtaining there. That universality already corresponds, in an overall sense, to the material reality existing there. This is so because the experiences of particular applications from which it was derived (to a great extent) have given lessons already validated by objective reality. It does not replace the particularities of concrete conditions. But it can shed light on them and be of guidance to grasp them.[27] A creative application of MLM already contains universality precisely because of this guidance. Its verification through practice in a particular material reality, the concrete conditions of a country, in turn enriches the universality of Marxism.
The Avakianist’s have as usual pulled words out of their context. And in that process they revealed how their reduction of Marxist fundamentals to a matter of method eliminates its universal truth. Let us repeat their words, “He does not argue they are universal because they are universally true, but rather because they correspond to, or were based upon, the “fundamentals” of Marxism.” This raises the question of the content of Marxist fundamentals, of ideology. Do they, as such, contain universality? Is that universality true? The logical conclusion of the RCP’s arguments leads to a negative, on both counts. But they are wrong. The basic principles of MLM contain universal truth. In fact, that is why MLM can be applied in diverse conditions and fields. However this universality is not something static, some readymade answer explaining reality.
How is this to be understood? As Lenin pointed out, every law ‘freezes’ reality. It is incomplete, relative. Therefore, the application of MLM laws or principles to chart out the course of revolution in any country also calls for enriching, developing, the conceptual understanding of those laws. Otherwise it would be cutting the feet to suit the ‘shoe’ of laws. This is the point about creative application. In fact, creative application of MLM precisely calls for such conceptual leaps in grasping the universal laws established by MLM. Thus, through its application in unravelling and handling the specific laws of a particular revolution, the universal laws of MLM themselves become more complete, more capable of grasping the complex, contradictory, motion of the whole human society.[28]
We will now proceed to examine another consequence of the RCP’s approach. This is its mechanical equation of the realms of natural sciences and social sciences. My argument[29] on the qualitative distinction between the natural sciences and social sciences and the error of simply extending the methods of the former into the latter has been contested by the Avakianists.[30]
Marxism takes practice as the criterion of truth. It insists that social theory must be verified by objective reality. This constitutes the foundation of its claim to be scientific. It shares this scientific method in common with the natural sciences. But if this is taken to the extreme of equating both and ignoring their qualitative difference, it would amount to a form of mechanical thinking. Marx was well aware of this danger. He insisted on the distinction between the precision possible in the analysis of material economic conditions as compared to that of ideological forms.[31] Later on, tendencies which overlooked the importance of this insight emerged and became entrenched. Stalin’s argument that the ‘science of history of society’ “…can become as precise a science as, let us say, biology…” was an example.”[32] It is one thing to say that Marxism has made the study of history scientific. But it’s quite another to claim that Marxist historiography can attain as much precision as a natural science. Apart from the paucity of factual material, historical study of any society can never do without the study and interpretation of its ideological forms.
The views of the RCP display a repeat of Stalin’s error. It is rendered even grosser through Avakian’s endorsement of Karl Popper’s criteria of ‘being scientific’. For Popper, a theory is scientific only if can be challenged by testing for its falsifiability. Avakian accepts this. Popper’s had asserted that Marxism is unscientific because it isn’t falsifiable. Avakian replies by insisting that it is indeed falsifiable ‘in a fundamental and essential sense’. He then enumerates examples where Marxism has withstood the test of falsifiability.[33]At a first reading this would appear as a valid refutation of Popper. But closer examination will show something else. Recollect Mao’s observation that despite having correct ideas representatives of the advanced class may still suffer defeat because of their comparative weakness. By its very logic, the criterion of falsifiability can never comprehend this paradox. For it, failure is simply failure and conclusive proof of being unscientific.[34] Avakian’s defence of Marxism is thus fatally flawed. Based as it is on an uncritical acceptance of Popper’s criterion, it ultimately goes to undermine the claim of Marxism to truth. The roots of this lie in his failure to properly grasp the qualitative distinction between the natural sciences and social sciences. [35]
Avakian is quite caught up with this confusion. He writes, “Communism, it could be said, is not simply a science, in the sense that it does involve other elements, including morality, which are, strictly speaking, outside of the province of science. But all this cannot be divorced from science; and it all ultimately and fundamentally rests on, as well as needing to be continually regrounded in, what is actually true, as determined by a scientific approach and method, and no other.”[36] Astonishingly enough, this is said while claiming to present a correct understanding on the relation between science and philosophy. Apart from ‘morality’, the ‘other elements’ mentioned by Avakian as constituting communist philosophy are ‘outlook and method’. Among them ‘method’ obviously cannot be ‘strictly kept’ outside the province of science. The distinctly philosophical is thereby reduced to ‘morality and outlook’. Thus what is advanced as the defence of scientific methods in philosophy ends up as the pauperisation of philosophy.
Philosophy is no doubt indissolubly bound up with material reality and the sciences that unravel it. But empirical sciences are only one of the sources of philosophy. It emerges from all the realms of human existence, including art and culture, and draws sustenance from them. Its roots lie not only in the human-nature interaction but also in those of oneself with one’s own material and spiritual existence. The greatness of Marxist philosophy lies in its unbound capacity to comprehend and address this totality in all its dazzling particularities.
We must adopt scientific methods in philosophy - “the science of thought and its laws—formal logic and dialectics.” But philosophy cannot be treated as a natural science. Avakian advocates this wrong view. Criticising the concept of ‘scientific ideology’ he states, “It has been pointed out that this argument amounts to an attempt to create ideology and philosophy which stand outside or above science—ideology and philosophy which are, in the words of this criticism, "a higher level of abstraction" than science.”[37] Avakian attributes all sorts of deviations to the term ‘scientific ideology’. What he fails to examine is the commonly understood meaning of this term – an ideology that is scientific because it accords to reality. Ideology was taken to mean the body of principles and method of Marxism from the 2nd international period onwards. Earlier, for example in ‘German Ideology’, it was mostly understood as ‘false consciousness’, an inverted grasp of reality. Current developments, including claims about Thoughts, Paths and Syntheses, pose the necessity to re-examine the present understanding on ideology as such and probe how far it can be scientific and how much of it would be ‘false consciousness’. But let’s leave that aside for now and get on with Avakian’s argument.
What is scientific abstraction? Theoretical abstractions made in science are derived from particular laws discovered in specific fields of scientific enquiry. Therefore, it is meaningless to speak about an abstraction of ‘science as such’ and debate its position. Compared to scientific abstractions in specific fields, the abstractions of ideology and philosophy certainly do represent a higher level. This is so because the universal categories they put forward are themselves derived from a diverse set of universalities contained in laws governing specific fields of social life and natural phenomena. An ideology or philosophy will be wrong in its abstractions if they are not grounded in natural and social reality. But that doesn’t change the fact that they represent a higher level of abstraction. [38] Avakian confuses the scientific method for natural sciences and drains out the distinctiveness of philosophy and ideology. This is a manifestation of scienticism, a variant of positivism. The one to one equation of natural sciences and social sciences seen in the RCP flows from just such mistaken thinking and in turn bolsters it. Avakian prides to imagine himself and his supporters as a team of scientists setting out to transform the world. Fortunately for us, the ‘green pastures’ of natural and social reality readily provide the means, and Maoism the tools, to resist and overturn this scienticist project.

A RATIONALIST CRITIQUE OF RELIGION

With scienticism as a prominent trait it shouldn’t be surprising to see Avakianism indulge in crass rationalism while dealing with religion. He writes, “You pull one little thread and it all unravels – that’s religion, religious absolutism. This is the point I keep hammering at Christian Fascists: If one thing in the Bible is wrong, then their whole case is sunk…”. Be cautioned! If you thought this was the height of wishful thinking, the gem is yet to come: “I have some strategic thinking about how the way you can get to the mass base of these Christian Fascists is by hammering at the foundations of it…hammering in the ideological sphere.”[39] Well, there is already a long-standing, acknowledged, claimant for that. ‘Hammering religion in the ideological sphere’ has been the ‘strategic thinking’ of rationalism and its proponents for quite some centuries now. They have been literally tearing at religion all over, not just pulling at one or the other thread. Not merely one, a huge lot of things in the Bible and all those other religious texts have been proven wrong. But religion and religious absolutism still remain to be “unravelled” (whatever that may mean). If at all, they have been ‘ravelling up’ a lot of things in recent times!
The Marxist understanding on religion is well explained in these words of Marx, “Religion is the general theory of this world, its encyclopaedic compendium, its logic in popular form, its spiritual point d’honneur, its enthusiasm, its moral sanction, its solemn complement, and its universal basis of consolation and justification. It is the fantastic realisation of the human essence since the human essence has not acquired any true reality. The struggle against religion is, therefore, indirectly the struggle against that world whose spiritual aroma is religion. Religious suffering is, at one and the same time, the expression of real suffering and a protest against real suffering. Religion is the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions. It is the opium of the people.”[40] These words beautifully and scientifically grasp the material and spiritual underpinnings of religion. It thus cautions against assuming that religious faith can be controverted merely with rational argument. The scientific understanding on the role played by religion has since been deepened through studies in diverse fields. Its historical role in the creation and development of morality and social ties and its imprint in the human brain are now better known. All of this has surely confirmed the Marxist understanding on religion. But they also demand that Marxists move beyond a simplistic description of religion as something born of ignorance and secured by the interests of the ruling classes.
It would seem that Avakian is at least engaged with the material grounding of religion. Yet the few instances where he tries at a materialist explanation are as mechanical as is his ideological approach on religion. One of these is his equation between proletarianisation and the ‘decrease of religion’. The reverse, de-proletarianisation under conditions of globalisation, is held to be a prime cause leading to ‘gravitation toward religion, and in particular religious fundamentalism’.[41] This simply flies against facts. One could give any number of instances where overwhelming sections of a growing proletariat remained religious even though they were unionised and involved in class struggle. But, more than that, this Avakianist thesis blocks us off from grasping the reasons for the decline of the secular among the proletariat, a phenomenon that appeared well before the advent of globalisation. The secular, the progressive, was not pushed out by religious trends in tandem with de-proletarianisation. Rather, religious revivalism and fundamentalism grew up in the space vacated by their weakening.
If this is understood properly we will be drawn to a meaningful analysis of the particularities of religious phenomena such as fundamentalism and revivalism. Whereas, if the vulgar materialist thesis of ‘de-proletarianisation leading to growth of religious fundamentalism’ is accepted, we will be lead away from this important task. Specificities of ideological tasks in this field will be denied. The blanket solution will be that of ‘hammering away’. Militant materialist exposure of religious thought is certainly needed. But it can never stand in for a Marxist critique of existing religious phenomena.
In his discussion on the material grounds of religious fundamentalism, Avakian points to the destabilising impact of globalisation in the Third World. This, coupled with most people in urban areas ending up in the informal economy, is seen as a major reason for “…many people … turning to religious fundamentalism to try to give them an anchor, in the midst of all this dislocation and upheaval.”[42] Let’s take a closer look at this. The conditions he describes can explain why religious faith is getting strengthened among the oppressed, in a context of weakening of the Left. But why do they turn to fundamentalism? Why not to some other religious trend? In Avakian’s scheme all this would be irrelevant. Earlier we had seen how he casually places religion and religious absolutism in the same bracket.
The fall out of this rationalism is seen in his dismissal of Islamic resistance movements in Iraq and Afghanistan as a “reactionary pole” representing a “historically outmoded strata among colonized and oppressed humanity”. The imperialist economism contained in this position has already been dealt with in an earlier section. Here we will examine some theoretical aspects. Islamic fundamentalism certainly is a historically outmoded ideology. But does it represent historically outmoded social strata? Not necessarily.  Islamic fundamentalism itself is not a single entity. Some of its streams are quite petty bourgeois, rural and urban, even ‘modern’ in education. The petty bourgeoisie of an oppressed country is an important national force. It can play a reactionary role. But it is by no means historically outmoded. Such petty bourgeois class composition of the core is one important reason why some fundamentalist movements are able to connect with the broad masses and don the mantle of legitimate resistance. If the Maoists are to challenge these forces and assume leadership of the struggle it won’t do to merely expose the reactionary content of their program. They must address and unravel the enigma of a modern class, generally progressive, fiercely advocating an outmoded and reactionary ideology and achieving representation of national resistance through it. Instead of merely describing how these forces are “… returning to, and enforcing with a vengeance, traditional relations, customs, ideas and values …”[43], they must seek out the particularities of this phenomenon which give it its fascist character. [44]
Secondly, all the Islamic religious movements that have emerged or strengthened in the Third World in recent times are neither fundamentalist nor revivalist. A lot of ideological churning is going on among Muslims, and that is true of the religious sphere too. Though liberation theology trends are still practically non-existent, that is not the case with reformist ones. Some among them are quite infatuated with Western democracy and modernisation. This a reflection of the illusions created among a section of the middle and lower classes by globalisation. They see in it a means to economic elevation. This is another aspect of globalisation’s dynamics. The pro-West political stance of some trends of Islamic reformism facilitates the appropriation of anti-imperialism by fundamentalism. It in turn bolsters its claims on being the true rendering of Islam and helps it block the democratisation of Islamic belief. Maoist ideological intervention will have to address all of these aspects if it is to make headway. Obviously, such complexities are simply beyond Avakian’s thought.
Finally, Avakian’s arguments totally fail to identify and locate the major role played by national sentiments and culture in the growth of Third World fundamentalism. He writes, “An additional factor in all this is that, in the Third World, these massive and rapid changes and dislocations are occurring in the context of domination and exploitation by foreign imperialists— and this is associated with “local” ruling classes which are economically and politically dependent on and subordinate to imperialism, and are broadly seen as the corrupt agents of an alien power, who also promote the “decadent culture of the West.” This, in the short run, can strengthen the hand of fundamentalist religious forces and leaders who frame opposition to the “corruption” and “Western decadence” of the local ruling classes, and the imperialists to which they are beholden, in terms of returning to, and enforcing with a vengeance, traditional relations, customs, ideas and values which themselves are rooted in the past and embody extreme forms of exploitation and oppression.”[45] By this logic, what is seen is nothing more than of a bunch of reactionaries making use of popular anger against an alien power and its servitors. There is no effort to grapple with why “traditional relations, customs, ideas and values … rooted in the past” can be so readily promoted and made acceptable in this modern age by the fundamentalists. Its articulation, spread and assimilation as a national discourse is nowhere acknowledged. But that is precisely why the fundamentalists are able to disseminate them without much resistance. For sure, they embody extreme forms of exploitation and domination. However, this doesn’t controvert their quality of being part of that culture. Here, the sources of Avakian’s error extend beyond his rationalism to his economist views on the national question. Be that as it is, we must go deeper into the implications of what was said above.
Understanding the ‘national’ claim of fundamentalism helps us locate the failure of Maoists to uphold the national banner in oppressed countries coupled with a superficial identification of comprador modernisation with secularisation of society as one of the reasons for its strengthening. The latter is no less important than the former.  Its ambit of influence goes beyond the boundaries of the Third World and encompasses significant sections of progressive people in imperialist countries. It even extends to the Maoist camp.[46]
Furthermore, awareness of the ‘national’ claim of fundamentalism helps us grasp that “…unless the spiritual space occupied by fundamentalism is retaken with the enlightening vision of an all-round liberation, a vibrant national, secular culture and a new society free of exploitation, unless the physical space now occupied by fundamentalist resistance is regained under the revolutionary banners of a peoples’ war, the Maoists are not going to succeed.”[47] We must add, unless they thoroughly repudiate Avakianism they will not even reach anywhere near these tasks.


[1]Its baneful influence continues to prey on the movement. The term ‘instrumentalism’ is used by some to indicate this subjectivism.
[2]‘Epistemology’, op. cit.
[3]May 16 Circular of the Central Committee of the Communist Party of China on the Great Proletarian Cultural Revolution, emphasis added. <http://www.marxists.org/subject/china/documents/cpc/cc_gpcr.htm>
[4]A similar error is seen in the RCP’s reply to the ‘9 Letters to Comrades’ put out by Mike Elly and others of the Kasama Project. (<http://revcom.us/a/polemics/NineLettersResponse.pdf>) They wrote, “Quoting Mike Ely, “An article from Peking Review’s revolutionary days writes, ‘Truth has a class character. There have never been truths commonly regarded as “indisputable” by all classes in the field of social science.’ Why is that wrong?” …Yes, Mike Ely, the above statements are, in fact, wrong…the existence of fierce class struggle over what is accepted as truth does not imply that truth itself has a class character…Truth itself is objective, and should be assessed by whether it corresponds to objective reality, as can be known and understood in the most scientific and materialist way.” Where the Peking Review article points to the dispute between classes over what is true in the field of social sciences, the RCP evades it and speaks of the objective character of truth. Is the objective world the same for the proletariat and the bourgeoisie? Yes it is, there is only one material reality. But each of these classes realise, grasp, this reality in different ways. The RCP’s example, Mao’s statement on the existence of classes and the need for continuing class struggle in socialist society, is illustrative. They ask, “How is this “proletarian truth” untrue for the bourgeoisie?”. Well it certainly is. To start with, the ‘new bourgeoisie’ simply refuses to acknowledge itself as such. In its consciousness it is as proletarian, over even more so, than its opponent. They do not suppress the fact because it doesn’t ‘benefit their fundamental interests’. Those interests, their class character, prevent them from realising it.
[6]Response…,’ emphasis added, op. cit.
[7]In another instance they say, “Because the proletariat as a class has no need to cover up the fundamental character of human society, dialectical and historical materialism corresponds to its fundamental interests …”, (What Is Bob Avakian’s New Synthesis?-Part 2, italicised in original, underlining added, op. cit.) Here, what is inherent to dialectical materialism, its proletarian class nature, is made into a matter of correspondence.
[8]Ibid.
[9]For the record, Avakian had a better position before he ventured to break away from Maoism. In 1997 he wrote, “”MLM … recognises and deals with the particularity of many different contradictions, but it does so from the standpoint and with the methodology of the class-conscious proletariat, because the stand, viewpoint, and method representing the proletariat is both partisan and true. It reflects the interests of a particular class and it reflects objective reality.” ‘MLM Is Partisan--And True’, Revolutionary Worker #908, May 25, 1997, emphasis added. <http://www.revcom.us/a/v19/905-09/908/bamlm2.htm>
[10]‘Response…’, emphasis added, op. cit.
[11]“… Marx and Engels, responding to the needs of the revolutionary struggle of the proletariat, personally participated in the practice of the revolutionary struggles of the time, summed up the experience of the workers' movement, began a long and difficult programme of theoretical research, and, critically absorbing what was rational in the cultural and scientific achievements of humanity, created Marxism.” (Basic Understanding of the Communist Party of China, Norman Bethune Institute, Toronto, 1976, page 28, emphasis added. http://www.marxists.org/history/erol/china/basic-understanding.pdf)  This all-round account of the emergence of Marxism stands in sharp contrast to the shrivelled up presentation of the RCP, gutted of class struggle: “Marx and Engels developed their worldview not mainly out of any specific practice they were engaged in and still less out of the activities in “a particular country”. As Lenin emphasised in his well-known article “The Three Component Parts of Marxism,” Marxism was forged from elements of French socialism, British political economy and German philosophy.”, ‘Response...’, op. cit.
[12]Had Marx and Engels sought to construct rather than discover truth, however well-intentioned and “partisan” they may have been, they would have succeeded no further than the various utopian socialists and other reformers who decried the injustice of class exploitation but were unable to understand wherein lay the roots of class exploitation or by what process such society could be transcended., ibid.
[13]Ibid.
[14]A Critique Of The CRC, CPI (M-L) Line, 2.1, April 1997, henceforth ‘Critique…’.
[15]Ibid, emphasis added.
[16]This is a persistent position of Avakianism. Avakian wrote, “Theory is the dynamic factor in ideology.” (The Need For Communists To Be...Communists’, Bob Avakian, emphasis added, henceforth ‘Need…’. www.revcom.us/a/038/avakian-need-for-communists.htm)
[17]Response…’, op. cit.
[18]Ibid, emphasis added.
[19]Karl Popper, for instance, declared, “Marxism is fundamentally a method.”, quoted in ‘Karl Popper and the Social Sciences’, William A Gorton, State University of New York, 2006, page 83.
[20]The CRC, CPI (ML) drew attention to the importance of grasping philosophy. But its liberalism soon led to treating dialectical materialism merely as a methodology which can equally serve any class. The proletarian bias of this philosophy was in effect denied.”, ‘Critique…’, 3.1, April, 1997, op. cit.
[21]Response…’, op. cit. Though it is also characterised as ‘… a product …’ this is already circumscribed by ‘method and approach’.
[22]‘Socialist…’, emphasis added, op. cit.
[23]‘Speech at National Conference on Propaganda Work’, SW Vol  5, page 434, emphasis added, op. cit.
[24]Avakian has suggested a different approach, “Of course, it is possible that a scientific theory is true—correctly reflects reality—in its main and essential aspects, but is shown to be incorrect in certain secondary aspects—and, in accordance with that, some of its particular predictions prove not to be true. And when that is the case, the application of the scientific method leads to a further development of the theory—through the discarding, or modifying, of certain aspects and the addition of new elements into the theory.”(‘Making…’, Part 1, Marxism as a Science…’, Revolution #105, October 21, 2007, op. cit.)  This is founded on the assumption that the Popperist concept of ‘falsifiability’ is fully applicable to Marxism. This is a problematic proposition. We will be examining it later on.
[25]‘Socialist…’, op. cit.
[26]Response…’, op. cit.
[27]To give an example, the Communist International pointed out that imperialism transforms and makes feudalism its social base in an oppressed country. That lesson was derived from the social analyses of numerous colonial and semi-colonial countries. As such it contains a universal truth that helps communists in preparing their programs and guiding their practice.
[28]‘The Fight to Establish Maoism’, Ajith, Naxalbari No: 2. <http://bannedthought.net/India/CPI-ML-Naxalbari/Naxalbari-Magazine/Naxalbari-02.pdf> 
[29]“Marxism is also a science.  So the comparison is being made with natural sciences, where new discoveries have led to re-examination of fundamental concepts. This comparison overlooks the qualitative distinction between the natural and social sciences. The distinct character of the latter is their class partisanship. While social facts are part of objective reality, the process of identifying them and seeking out truth, as well as the extent to which truth can be synthesised, are intimately bound up with class stand. Whether something claimed as new is really new is itself a matter of class struggle, in theory as well as in practice. All of this rules out a simple extension of the methods of natural sciences into the re-examining of Marxist positions.” (‘Socialist…’, emphasis added, op. cit.) Lenin stated, “… in modern society the latter [political economy] is as much a partisan science as is epistemology.” (‘Materialism and Emperio-criticism’, Chapter 6.4, LCW 14, words in square brackets added. <archive/lenin/works/1908/mec/six4.htm>) Further on, Mao drew attention to the role of ideology in aiding or preventing the acquisition of knowledge even in the natural sciences. He noted, “As for the natural sciences, there are two aspects. The natural sciences as such have no class nature, but the question of who studies and makes use of them does.”(‘Beat Back the Attacks of the Bourgeois Rightists’, MSW 5, pages 460-1.<http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/mao/selected-works/volume-5/mswv5_65.htm>)
[30]As usual, it begins with a distortion. For instance, my views on the methodological implications of the qualitative difference between the two realms is twisted around to charge me with “refusing” the necessity of re-examining fundamental principles in the social sciences. (‘Response…’, op. cit.) In an even more vulgar display of Avakianist craft K.J.F writes, “Ajith argues that because of Marxism's "proletarian stand and partisanship", it cannot (and should not attempt to) conform to the scientific method used in the natural sciences.”(‘Polemical…’, emphasis added, op. cit.)
[31] “With the change of the economic foundation the entire immense superstructure is more or less rapidly transformed. In considering such transformations a distinction should always be made between the material transformation of the economic conditions of production, which can be determined with the precision of natural science, and the legal, political, religious, aesthetic or philosophic — in short, ideological forms in which men become conscious of this conflict and fight it out.” ‘Preface of a Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy’, emphasis added.
<http://marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1859/critique-pol-economy/preface.htm> It must be noted that what Marx is dealing with here is the comparative differences in precision. The diverse fields of material reality studied by the natural sciences themselves exhibit various levels of possible precision. But this does not negate the qualitative difference in this matter between the natural and social sciences.
[32]Dialectical and Historical Materialism, Stalin, emphasis added.
[33]“There are definitely things in Marxism that are falsifiable. For example, dialectical materialism. If the world were made up of something other than matter in motion—if that could be shown—then clearly Marxism in its fundamentals, in its essence and at its core, would be falsified, proven wrong. Or, if it could be shown that, yes, all reality consists of matter, but that some forms of matter do not change, do not have internal contradiction and motion and development—that too would be a fundamental refutation of dialectical materialism. But none of that has been shown.” ‘Making…’,   Part 1, Marxism as a Science, op. cit.
[34]Despite his insistence on the test of falsifiability (i.e. verification based on objective reality) Popper finally ended up posing ‘criticism of theory’ as the ultimate test. But that is another matter.
[35]Avakian’s arguments are the mirror opposite of those advanced by Venu. In his criticism of Popper, Venu argued “…the law of dialectical materialism which states that the unity and struggle of opposites is operating in all the processes in the universe cannot be proved at the level of empirical science. Whether this law of dialectical materialism operates in any particular branch of science can be examined and found out by that particular branch. But, no branch of science can say that it is a law applicable to the whole universe...Thus, the law of the unity and struggle of opposites, the cornerstone of Marxist world outlook, is never proved completely at the level of science.”(‘Philosophical Problems of Revolution’, K. Venu, Vijayan Book Stall, Kottayam, 1982, pages 107-08, emphasis added) As seen here, his rebuttal was based on recognition of the qualitative difference between the realms of philosophy and science. This is true. But it failed in its task because the issue is not one of being ‘proved completely’. Failure to pass the test of objectivity even in a single field of the natural sciences would be sufficient to overturn the claims of dialectical materialism.
[36]‘Ruminations and Wranglings - A Correct Understanding Of The Relation Between Science And Philosophy’, underlining in original, italics added, op. cit.
[37] Ibid. - ‘Communism as a Science—Not a "Scientific Ideology’, emphasis added, op .cit. 
[38]In his biographical sketch of Marx Lenin wrote “Dialectical materialism "does not need any philosophy standing above the other sciences. "” (Selected Works, Volume1, emphasis added.
<http://marxists.org/archive/lenin/works/1914/granat/ch02.htm>) This has been a consistent position of Marxism right from the very beginning. It needs to be clarified that what is meant by ‘standing above’ in this quote is the claim of pre-Marxian philosophies to be the all-embracing source of knowledge for all domains, natural and social. 
[39] ‘Observations...’, page 77, op. cit.
[40] Introduction, A Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right.
[41]In Avakian’s words, “Mike Davis, who has his limitations but also has some important insights, wrote an article where he spoke about how in the nineteenth and early twentieth century when people were driven off the land in the countries where capitalism was rising, they were more or less—not evenly and smoothly but more or less—integrated into the proletariat. And the proletarianisation of these people led to a decrease in religion. But the phenomenon in the world today is in significant measure the opposite: people being driven from the countryside to the cities, or flushed out of the proletariat, if you will, and being herded into these massive shantytowns, existing in this “disarticulated” kind of situation—this has given rise to the reverse phenomenon of the growth, the significant dramatic growth, of gravitation toward religion, and in particular religious fundamentalism.”, (‘Basis…Changing Material Conditions and the Growth of Religious Fundamentalism’, op. cit.  
[42]Why Is Religious Fundamentalism Growing in Today’s World—And What Is the Real Alternative?, henceforth ‘Religious Fundamentalism…’ <http://www.revcom.us/a/104/avakian-religion-en.html>
[43]Ibid. 
[44]A preliminary attempt in this direction can be seen in ‘Islamic…’, op. cit. Incidentally, this article, published in 2007, directly took on Avakian’s thesis on ‘ the two outmodeds’. The Avakianists have yet to ‘engage’ with it.
[45]‘Religious Fundamentalism ... ‘, op. cit.
[46]Uncritical adulation of works of art with a ‘modern’ ethos originating from the Westernised urban middle class or elite circles in the Third World as expressions of progressive thought is an example of this tendency.
[47]‘Islamic…’, op. cit.

No comments:

Post a Comment